Long before psychology became a science, philosophers debated this issue. As discussed in Chapter 1, Berkeley took the position that a two- dimensional retina was logically incapable of directly yielding depth perception because it could receive only a two-dimensional image. We must learn to gauge the distance of things by a process of association. Accommodation and convergence are cues that ultimately become reliable signs of distance because we reach for or move toward things and this teaches us how to interpret these signs. Others emphasized inborn characteristics of mind such as the predisposition to locate things in three-dimensional space. If we did not by nature tend to organize the perceptual world spatially, so the argument goes, how could we ever learn about depth localization? In trying to resolve this issue by experimentation, psychologists have historically encountered the same problems they have in attempting to discover the origins of constancy. Except in response to the new "habituation" method (to be discussed in Chapter 5), newborn animals, human or otherwise, can only "tell" us what they perceive through performance on behavioral tests of learning, of which very immature organisms are usually not capable, while rearing animals without vision until they are mature enough to test leads to severe deterioration of the visual nervous system and prevention of normal maturation.